Cosmological
Kalam
(P1) Everything that begins to exist has a cause. Something cannot come into being from nothing.
(P2) The universe began to exist.
(C1) Therefore, the universe has a cause.
(P3) If the universe has a cause, then an uncaused, personal Creator of the universe exists who sans the universe is beginningless, changeless, immaterial, timeless, spaceless, and enormously powerful. Personal: The first state of the universe cannot have a scientific explanation, since there is nothing before it, and therefore, it cannot be accounted for in terms of laws operating on initial conditions. It can only be accounted for in terms of an unembodied mind and his free volitions, a personal explanation.
(P4) The universe has a cause.
(C2) Therefore, an uncaused, personal Creator of the universe exists who sans the universe is beginningless, changeless, immaterial, timeless, spaceless, and enormously powerful.
Contingency
(P1) Anything that exists has an explanation of its existence, either in the necessity of its own nature or in an external cause. (modest PSR) 17th century Leibniz original Principle of Sufficient Reason (PSR): "no fact can be real or existent, no statement true, unless there be a sufficient reason why it is so and not otherwise."
(P2) If the universe has an explanation of its existence, that explanation is grounded in a necessary being.
(P3) The universe exists.
(C1) Therefore, the universe has an explanation of its existence (from P1, P3).
(C2) Therefore, the explanation of the existence of the universe is grounded in a necessary being (from P2, C1).
(C3) Therefore, a necessary being exists (God).
Teleological
Cosmic Fine-Tuning
(P1) The fine-tuning of the universe is due to either physical necessity, chance, or design.
(P2) It is not due to physical necessity or chance.
(C1) Therefore, it is due to design.
Applicability of Mathematics
(P1) If God does not exist, the applicability of mathematics to the physical world is just a happy coincidence.
(P2) The applicability of mathematics to the physical world is not just a happy coincidence.
(C1) Therefore, God exists.
Moral & Agency
The Moral Argument
(P1) If God does not exist, objective moral values and duties do not exist.
(P2) Objective moral values and duties do exist.
(C1) Therefore, God exists.
Free-Thinking Argument
(P1) If robust naturalism is true, then God or things like God do not exist. Robust naturalism is the idea that only physical things exist.
(P2) If God or things like God do not exist, then humanity does not freely think in the libertarian sense. via Naturalistic Determinism
(P3) If humanity does not freely think in the libertarian sense, then humanity is never epistemically responsible.
(P4) Humanity is occasionally epistemically responsible.
(C1) Therefore, humanity freely thinks in the libertarian sense. (from P3 and P4, modus tollens)
(C2) Therefore, God or things like God exist. (from P2 and C1, modus tollens)
(C3) Therefore, robust naturalism is false. (from P1 and C2, modus tollens)
(P5) The biblical account of reality is one possible explanation for the existence of God, things like God, and the libertarian freedom of humanity.
(P6) If the biblical account provides a better explanation of these facts than alternative accounts, then it is reasonable to accept it as the best explanation.
(C4) Therefore, if the biblical account provides the best explanation, it is reasonable to accept it. (from P5 and P6, abduction)
Ontological
Maximal Greatness
(P1) It is possible that a maximally great being exists.
(P2) If it is possible that a maximally great being exists, then a maximally great being exists in some possible world.
(P3) If a maximally great being exists in some possible world, then it exists in every possible world.
(P4) If a maximally great being exists in every possible world, then it exists in the actual world.
(P5) If a maximally great being exists in the actual world, then a maximally great being exists.
(C1) Therefore, a maximally great being exists.
Miracles
Explanatory Argument: Minimal Facts
(P1) The most reasonable explanation for a set of historical facts is the one that best accounts for all the evidence.
(P2) There exists a set of minimal facts (Jesus's crucifixion, the disciples' reported experiences, their transformation from fearful to bold, and Paul's conversion) that are accepted by virtually all critical scholars in the field, based on standard historical methodologies.
(P3) Against all other theories, the resurrection theory best accounts for these widely accepted minimal facts.
(P4) A resurrection from the dead requires supernatural intervention beyond natural laws.
(P5) Supernatural intervention that suspends natural laws requires the existence of a supernatural being with power over nature.
(P6) Such a supernatural being with power over nature corresponds to what we mean by "God."
(C1) Therefore, the resurrection of Jesus is the most reasonable explanation for these widely accepted minimal facts.
(C2) Therefore, God's existence is the most reasonable explanation for the resurrection of Jesus.
Bayesian Argument
(P1) If a set of specific historical facts (F) is overwhelmingly better explained by one hypothesis (H) than by any plausible alternative hypothesis under the negation of H (~H), then those facts provide strong cumulative evidence for H, particularly when analyzed probabilistically using a Bayesian framework. Bayes' theorem gives a mathematical rule for inverting conditional probabilities, allowing one to find the probability of a cause given its effect. The strength of the evidence is measured by the ratio of the probability of the facts given H to the probability of the facts given ~H (the Bayes factor), with a very high ratio indicating strong confirmation for H.
(P2) There exists a set of specific historical facts (F) concerning the period immediately following Jesus' death that are well-attested in historical sources which, despite minor variations common in historical documents, can be regarded as basically historically reliable, comparable to other secular history sources. These facts include the testimony of the women regarding the empty tomb and their sight of the resurrected Christ (W), the testimony of the disciples regarding seeing Christ alive and their willingness to die for this testimony (D), and the conversion of Paul (P). The reliability of the Gospels and Acts as sources is supported by external evidence for early dating and eyewitness access, contrary to sweeping negative conclusions of form and redaction criticism, which are often driven by philosophical naturalism and based on flawed methodology like the argumentum ex silentio or circular reasoning. It is also almost universally acknowledged by scholars that Jesus died on the cross.
(P3) The hypothesis that Jesus miraculously rose from the dead (R) provides an overwhelmingly better explanation for the conjunction of these specific historical facts (F = W&D&P) than any plausible alternative hypothesis under the negation of R (~R). Alternative naturalistic explanations like the swoon theory, theft hypothesis, alternative burial theories, hallucination theory (individual or collective), and conspiracy theory are shown to be highly improbable, inadequate to explain the specific details of the evidence, or contradicted by the evidence itself (e.g., the disciples' willingness to die for a claim they knew was false is highly improbable). A generic objective vision theory under ~R also fails to account for the specific nature of the testimony. The cumulative Bayes factor P(W&D&P|R) / P(W&D&P|~R) is extremely large, with estimates for individual components being significant (e.g., P(W|R)/P(W|~R) at least 100, P(D|R)/P(D|~R) possibly 10³⁹ under independence assumption which may underestimate the true strength, P(P|R)/P(P|~R) at least 10³).
(P4) The resurrection of Jesus (R), if it occurred, is understood as a paradigm case of a miracle. The truth of R stands in a relation to the evidence (F) and to Christianity (C) and theism (T) such that the evidential force of F flows through R to T and C; thus, R acts as a conduit of evidence for T and C. Evidence that strongly supports R consequently provides strong support for T and C.
(C1) Therefore, based on the overwhelming cumulative evidence provided by the well-attested historical facts (W, D, P) which are vastly better explained by the hypothesis of the resurrection (R) than by any alternative, it is highly probable that Jesus miraculously rose from the dead (R), and this provides a strong cumulative case argument for the truth of Christianity (C) and, by extension, theism (T). This argument is not undermined by general skeptical strategies such as Hume's maxim, worldview objections, or the Principle of Dwindling Probabilities, which either require engaging with the specific evidence (which the critics often fail to do adequately) or are based on flawed probabilistic reasoning.